Justification of Critical Thinking: A Response to Whether Critical Thinking Only Applies to Free Society?

  • Cheng-Hsi Chen
Expand
  • Graduate Institute of Educational Administration, Pingtung University, Taiwan 9003, China

Online published: 2021-01-18

Abstract

Critical thinking can be regarded as the mainstream educational aim of the 20th century in Britain and America, and it reflects the rational tradition of western epistemology and the Kant enlightenment tradition of respecting persons in moral theory. From a pragmatic point of view, most scholars believe that critical thinking is a basic ability necessary to cope with the rapid changes of modern society. J. Dewey and R. S. Peters examined the exploratory significance of the concept of educational aim itself from a philosophical standpoint. McPeck argues that education implies critical thinking from the analysis of conditions of knowledge. Siegel argues critical thinking as an educational ideal from four dimensions: respect for students as persons, self-sufficiency and preparation for adulthood, initiation into the rational traditions, critical thinking and democratic life. Siegel's argument is based on the rational and liberal atmosphere, which has also caused some political philosophers to reflect on whether a democratic society can accept the non-critical thinking education of minorities. Steutel and Spieck summarize critical thinking involving three themes: political policy and legislation, conceptions of the good and the liberal-political framework, concepts of the good and their intrinsic value. They investigate three arguments which intend to justify critical thinking as an aim of education. In their arguments, the support argument explains the first and second themes, and the welfare argument covers more than the support argument to the second theme. However, these two arguments and the necessity argument still cannot fully prove the third theme concerning critical thinking as intrinsic value of good. In addition to promoting critical thinking in liberal society, the author attempts to argue that if minority groups do not violate significant common social values and do not restrict their children's participation in mainstream society, critical thinking is still a desirable educational value. However, mainstream culture should respect minority groups which do not identify the critical thinking as educational value. Regardless of whether we have justified it sufficiently or not, philosophical justification remains to be conducive to the manifestation of educational concepts, helps to embody the spirit of critical thinking, recognizes its possible limitations, and also has positive significance in educational practice.

Cite this article

Cheng-Hsi Chen . Justification of Critical Thinking: A Response to Whether Critical Thinking Only Applies to Free Society?[J]. Journal of East China Normal University(Educational Sciences), 2021 , 39(1) : 78 -93 . DOI: 10.16382/j.cnki.1000-5560.2021.01.007

References

null 陈振华. 批判性思维培养的模式之争及其启示. 高等教育研究, (2014). 35 (9), 56- 63.
null 董毓. 批判性思维三大误解辨析. 高等教育研究, (2012). 33 (11), 64- 70.
null 简成熙. 彼得斯对教育内在性目的之论证及其相关评析. 教育学术月刊, (2019). (1), 3- 15.
null 简成熙. 批判式思维与建构式思维的可能: 来自女性主义的反思. 教育学术月刊, (2020a). (5), 3- 15.
null 简成熙. 重构自主性作为教育目的: 中西耻感取向的积极意义. 湖南师范大学教育科学学报, (2020b). 19 (2), 64- 77.
null 简成熙. 批判式思维是否是普遍性思维能力? 环绕 McPeck 的相关论辩. 山西大学学报(哲社版), (2021). 44 (1), 85- 97.
null 教育哲学编写组. (2019). 教育哲学. 北京市: 高等教育出版社, 121-127.
null 彭正梅、邓莉. 迈向教育改革的核心: 培养作为21世纪技能核心的批判性思维技能. 教育发展研究, (2017). (24), 57- 63.
null 钱颖一. 批判性思维与创造性思维教育: 理念与实践. 清华大学教育研究, (2018). 2 (1), 63- 97.
null 苏慧丽、于伟. 否定性—儿童批判思维培养的前提问题. 教育学报, (2019). 15 (4), 26- 34.
null 温明丽. (1998). 批判性思考教学—哲学之旅. 台北: 师大书苑.
null 武宏志. 论批判性思维. 广州大学学报(社会科学版), (2004). 3 (11), 10- 16.
null 岳晓东. 批判思维的形成与培养. 教育研究, (2000). (8), 65- 69.
null 钟启泉. 批判性思维: 概念界定与教学方略. 全球教育展望, (2020). 49 (1), 3- 16.
null Bailin, S. Is critical thinking biased? Clarifications and implications. Educational Theory, (1995). 45 (2), 191- 197.
null Cuypers, S. E. Is personal autonomy first principle of education?. Journal of Philosophy of Education, (1992). 26 (1), 5- 17.
null Cuypers, S. E. Critical thinking, autonomy and practical reason. Journal of Philosophy of Education, (2004). 38 (1), 75- 90.
null Dearden, R. F., Hirst, P. H., & Peters, R. S. (eds.) (1972). Education and the development of reason. London: RKP.
null Dewey, J. (1966). Democracy and education. New York: The Free Press.
null Dworkin, R. (1978). Liberalism. In S. Hampshire(ed.), Public and private morality (113-143). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
null Ennis, R. A concept of critical thinking. Harvard Educational Review, (1962). 32 (1), 81- 111.
null Galston, W. A. (1991). Liberal purposes: Goods, virtues, and diversity in the liberal state. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
null Galston, W. A. Two concepts of liberalism. Ethics, (1995). 105, 516- 534.
null Garrison, J. Dangerous dualisms in Siegel’s theory of critical thinking: A Deweyan Pragmatist responds. Journal of Philosophy of Education, (1999). 33 (2), 213- 231.
null Gutmann, A. (1987). Democratic education. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
null Hare, W. (1999). Critical thinking as an aim of education. In R. Marples(ed.) The aims of education (85−99). New York and London: Routledge.
null Kymlicka, W. (1989). Liberalism, community, and culture. Oxford: Clarendon.
null Kymlicka, W. & Norman, W. (1995). Return of the citizen: A survey of recent work on citizenship theory. In R. Beiner(ed.). Theorizing citizenship (283−322). Albany: State University of New York Press.
null Kymlicka, W. (1996). Multicultural citizenship: A liberal theory of minority rights. Oxford: Clarendon.
null McLaughlin, T. H. Citizenship, diversity and education: A philosophical perspective. Journal of Moral Education, (1992). 21 (3), 235- 250.
null McPeck, J. E. (1981). Critical thinking and education. Oxford: Martin Robertson.
null Peters, R. S. (1973). The justification of education. In R. S. Peters (ed.). Philosophy of education (239−267). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
null Paul, R. (1993). Critical thinking: What every person needs in a rapidly changing world. Santa Rosa, Calif.: Foundation for critical thinking.
null Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
null Scheffler, I. (1960). The language of education. Springfield, Illinois: Charles C. Thomas.
null Scheffler, I. (1965). Conditions of knowledge: An introduction to epistemology and knowledge. Glenview, Illinois: Scott, Foresman and company.
null Scheffler, I. (1973). Reason and teaching. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
null Siegel, H. (1988). Educating reason: Rationality, critical thinking, and education. New York: Routledge.
null Siegel, H. (1997). Rationality redeemed? Further dialogues on an educational ideal. New York: Routledge.
null Siegel, H. (2017). Education’s epistemology: Rationality, diversity, and critical thinking. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
null Steutel, J. & Spiecker, B. (1999). Liberalism and critical thinking: on the relation between a political ideal and an aim of education. In Marples, R. (ed.). The aims of education (61−73). London: RKP.
null Waldron, J. (1993). Liberal rights: Collected papers 1981—1991. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
null White, J. (1973). Towards a compulsory curriculum. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
null White, J. (1982). The aims of education restated. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
null White, J. (1991). Education and the good life: Autonomy, altruism and the National curriculum. New York: Teachers College Press.
Outlines

/